HomeHome Intuitionistic Logic Explorer
Theorem List (p. 59 of 74)
< Previous  Next >
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version.

Mirrors  >  Metamath Home Page  >  ILE Home Page  >  Theorem List Contents  >  Recent Proofs       This page: Page List

Theorem List for Intuitionistic Logic Explorer - 5801-5900   *Has distinct variable group(s)
TypeLabelDescription
Statement
 
Theoremtposf2 5801 The domain and range of a transposition. (Contributed by NM, 10-Sep-2015.)
(Rel A → (𝐹:AB → tpos 𝐹:AB))
 
Theoremtposf12 5802 Condition for an injective transposition. (Contributed by NM, 10-Sep-2015.)
(Rel A → (𝐹:A1-1B → tpos 𝐹:A1-1B))
 
Theoremtposf1o2 5803 Condition of a bijective transposition. (Contributed by NM, 10-Sep-2015.)
(Rel A → (𝐹:A1-1-ontoB → tpos 𝐹:A1-1-ontoB))
 
Theoremtposfo 5804 The domain and range of a transposition. (Contributed by NM, 10-Sep-2015.)
(𝐹:(A × B)–onto𝐶 → tpos 𝐹:(B × A)–onto𝐶)
 
Theoremtposf 5805 The domain and range of a transposition. (Contributed by NM, 10-Sep-2015.)
(𝐹:(A × B)⟶𝐶 → tpos 𝐹:(B × A)⟶𝐶)
 
Theoremtposfn 5806 Functionality of a transposition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2015.)
(𝐹 Fn (A × B) → tpos 𝐹 Fn (B × A))
 
Theoremtpos0 5807 Transposition of the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 10-Sep-2015.)
tpos ∅ = ∅
 
Theoremtposco 5808 Transposition of a composition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2015.)
tpos (𝐹𝐺) = (𝐹 ∘ tpos 𝐺)
 
Theoremtpossym 5809* Two ways to say a function is symmetric. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2015.)
(𝐹 Fn (A × A) → (tpos 𝐹 = 𝐹x A y A (x𝐹y) = (y𝐹x)))
 
Theoremtposeqi 5810 Equality theorem for transposition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Sep-2015.)
𝐹 = 𝐺       tpos 𝐹 = tpos 𝐺
 
Theoremtposex 5811 A transposition is a set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Sep-2015.)
𝐹 V       tpos 𝐹 V
 
Theoremnftpos 5812 Hypothesis builder for transposition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Sep-2015.)
x𝐹       xtpos 𝐹
 
Theoremtposoprab 5813* Transposition of a class of ordered triples. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Sep-2015.)
𝐹 = {⟨⟨x, y⟩, z⟩ ∣ φ}       tpos 𝐹 = {⟨⟨y, x⟩, z⟩ ∣ φ}
 
Theoremtposmpt2 5814* Transposition of a two-argument mapping. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Sep-2015.)
𝐹 = (x A, y B𝐶)       tpos 𝐹 = (y B, x A𝐶)
 
2.6.17  Undefined values
 
Theorempwuninel2 5815 The power set of the union of a set does not belong to the set. This theorem provides a way of constructing a new set that doesn't belong to a given set. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Feb-2015.)
( A 𝑉 → ¬ 𝒫 A A)
 
Theorem2pwuninelg 5816 The power set of the power set of the union of a set does not belong to the set. This theorem provides a way of constructing a new set that doesn't belong to a given set. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Jan-2020.)
(A 𝑉 → ¬ 𝒫 𝒫 A A)
 
2.6.18  Functions on ordinals; strictly monotone ordinal functions
 
Theoremiunon 5817* The indexed union of a set of ordinal numbers B(x) is an ordinal number. (Contributed by NM, 13-Oct-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 5-Dec-2016.)
((A 𝑉 x A B On) → x A B On)
 
Syntaxwsmo 5818 Introduce the strictly monotone ordinal function. A strictly monotone function is one that is constantly increasing across the ordinals.
wff Smo A
 
Definitiondf-smo 5819* Definition of a strictly monotone ordinal function. Definition 7.46 in [TakeutiZaring] p. 50. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 15-Nov-2011.)
(Smo A ↔ (A:dom A⟶On Ord dom A x dom Ay dom A(x y → (Ax) (Ay))))
 
Theoremdfsmo2 5820* Alternate definition of a strictly monotone ordinal function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Mar-2013.)
(Smo 𝐹 ↔ (𝐹:dom 𝐹⟶On Ord dom 𝐹 x dom 𝐹y x (𝐹y) (𝐹x)))
 
Theoremissmo 5821* Conditions for which A is a strictly monotone ordinal function. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 15-Nov-2011.)
A:B⟶On    &   Ord B    &   ((x B y B) → (x y → (Ax) (Ay)))    &   dom A = B       Smo A
 
Theoremissmo2 5822* Alternative definition of a strictly monotone ordinal function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 12-Mar-2013.)
(𝐹:AB → ((B ⊆ On Ord A x A y x (𝐹y) (𝐹x)) → Smo 𝐹))
 
Theoremsmoeq 5823 Equality theorem for strictly monotone functions. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 16-Nov-2011.)
(A = B → (Smo A ↔ Smo B))
 
Theoremsmodm 5824 The domain of a strictly monotone function is an ordinal. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 16-Nov-2011.)
(Smo A → Ord dom A)
 
Theoremsmores 5825 A strictly monotone function restricted to an ordinal remains strictly monotone. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 16-Nov-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 5-Dec-2016.)
((Smo A B dom A) → Smo (AB))
 
Theoremsmores3 5826 A strictly monotone function restricted to an ordinal remains strictly monotone. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 19-Nov-2011.)
((Smo (AB) 𝐶 (dom AB) Ord B) → Smo (A𝐶))
 
Theoremsmores2 5827 A strictly monotone ordinal function restricted to an ordinal is still monotone. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Mar-2013.)
((Smo 𝐹 Ord A) → Smo (𝐹A))
 
Theoremsmodm2 5828 The domain of a strictly monotone ordinal function is an ordinal. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 12-Mar-2013.)
((𝐹 Fn A Smo 𝐹) → Ord A)
 
Theoremsmofvon2dm 5829 The function values of a strictly monotone ordinal function are ordinals. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 12-Mar-2013.)
((Smo 𝐹 B dom 𝐹) → (𝐹B) On)
 
Theoremiordsmo 5830 The identity relation restricted to the ordinals is a strictly monotone function. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 16-Nov-2011.)
Ord A       Smo ( I ↾ A)
 
Theoremsmo0 5831 The null set is a strictly monotone ordinal function. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 20-Nov-2011.)
Smo ∅
 
Theoremsmofvon 5832 If B is a strictly monotone ordinal function, and A is in the domain of B, then the value of the function at A is an ordinal. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 20-Nov-2011.)
((Smo B A dom B) → (BA) On)
 
Theoremsmoel 5833 If x is less than y then a strictly monotone function's value will be strictly less at x than at y. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 22-Nov-2011.)
((Smo B A dom B 𝐶 A) → (B𝐶) (BA))
 
Theoremsmoiun 5834* The value of a strictly monotone ordinal function contains its indexed union. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 22-Nov-2011.)
((Smo B A dom B) → x A (Bx) ⊆ (BA))
 
Theoremsmoiso 5835 If 𝐹 is an isomorphism from an ordinal A onto B, which is a subset of the ordinals, then 𝐹 is a strictly monotonic function. Exercise 3 in [TakeutiZaring] p. 50. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 24-Nov-2011.)
((𝐹 Isom E , E (A, B) Ord A B ⊆ On) → Smo 𝐹)
 
Theoremsmoel2 5836 A strictly monotone ordinal function preserves the epsilon relation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 12-Mar-2013.)
(((𝐹 Fn A Smo 𝐹) (B A 𝐶 B)) → (𝐹𝐶) (𝐹B))
 
2.6.19  "Strong" transfinite recursion
 
Syntaxcrecs 5837 Notation for a function defined by strong transfinite recursion.
class recs(𝐹)
 
Definitiondf-recs 5838* Define a function recs(𝐹) on On, the class of ordinal numbers, by transfinite recursion given a rule 𝐹 which sets the next value given all values so far. If we were assuming the law of the excluded middle, we would then build on top of that a form of recursion which has separate cases for the empty set, successor ordinals, and limit ordinals. This version allows the update rule to use all previous values, which is why it is described as "strong".

(Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Jan-2015.)

recs(𝐹) = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}
 
Theoremrecseq 5839 Equality theorem for recs. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Jan-2015.)
(𝐹 = 𝐺 → recs(𝐹) = recs(𝐺))
 
Theoremnfrecs 5840 Bound-variable hypothesis builder for recs. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Jan-2015.)
x𝐹       xrecs(𝐹)
 
Theoremtfrlem1 5841* A technical lemma for transfinite recursion. Compare Lemma 1 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 47. (Contributed by NM, 23-Mar-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.)
(φA On)    &   (φ → (Fun 𝐹 A ⊆ dom 𝐹))    &   (φ → (Fun 𝐺 A ⊆ dom 𝐺))    &   (φx A (𝐹x) = (B‘(𝐹x)))    &   (φx A (𝐺x) = (B‘(𝐺x)))       (φx A (𝐹x) = (𝐺x))
 
Theoremtfrlem3ag 5842* Lemma for transfinite recursion. This lemma just changes some bound variables in A for later use. (Contributed by NM, 9-Apr-1995.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}       (𝐺 V → (𝐺 Az On (𝐺 Fn z w z (𝐺w) = (𝐹‘(𝐺w)))))
 
Theoremtfrlem3a 5843* Lemma for transfinite recursion. Let A be the class of "acceptable" functions. The final thing we're interested in is the union of all these acceptable functions. This lemma just changes some bound variables in A for later use. (Contributed by NM, 9-Apr-1995.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}    &   𝐺 V       (𝐺 Az On (𝐺 Fn z w z (𝐺w) = (𝐹‘(𝐺w))))
 
Theoremtfrlem3 5844* Lemma for transfinite recursion. Let A be the class of "acceptable" functions. The final thing we're interested in is the union of all these acceptable functions. This lemma just changes some bound variables in A for later use. (Contributed by NM, 9-Apr-1995.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}       A = {gz On (g Fn z w z (gw) = (𝐹‘(gw)))}
 
Theoremtfrlem3-2 5845* Lemma for transfinite recursion which changes a bound variable (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Apr-2019.)
(Fun 𝐹 (𝐹x) V)       (Fun 𝐹 (𝐹g) V)
 
Theoremtfrlem3-2d 5846* Lemma for transfinite recursion which changes a bound variable (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Jul-2019.)
(φx(Fun 𝐹 (𝐹x) V))       (φ → (Fun 𝐹 (𝐹g) V))
 
Theoremtfrlem4 5847* Lemma for transfinite recursion. A is the class of all "acceptable" functions, and 𝐹 is their union. First we show that an acceptable function is in fact a function. (Contributed by NM, 9-Apr-1995.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}       (g A → Fun g)
 
Theoremtfrlem5 5848* Lemma for transfinite recursion. The values of two acceptable functions are the same within their domains. (Contributed by NM, 9-Apr-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}       ((g A A) → ((xgu xv) → u = v))
 
Theoremrecsfval 5849* Lemma for transfinite recursion. The definition recs is the union of all acceptable functions. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-May-2015.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}       recs(𝐹) = A
 
Theoremtfrlem6 5850* Lemma for transfinite recursion. The union of all acceptable functions is a relation. (Contributed by NM, 8-Aug-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-May-2015.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}       Rel recs(𝐹)
 
Theoremtfrlem7 5851* Lemma for transfinite recursion. The union of all acceptable functions is a function. (Contributed by NM, 9-Aug-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}       Fun recs(𝐹)
 
Theoremtfrlem8 5852* Lemma for transfinite recursion. The domain of recs is ordinal. (Contributed by NM, 14-Aug-1994.) (Proof shortened by Alan Sare, 11-Mar-2008.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}       Ord dom recs(𝐹)
 
Theoremtfrlem9 5853* Lemma for transfinite recursion. Here we compute the value of recs (the union of all acceptable functions). (Contributed by NM, 17-Aug-1994.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}       (B dom recs(𝐹) → (recs(𝐹)‘B) = (𝐹‘(recs(𝐹) ↾ B)))
 
Theoremtfr2a 5854 A weak version of transfinite recursion. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.)
𝐹 = recs(𝐺)       (A dom 𝐹 → (𝐹A) = (𝐺‘(𝐹A)))
 
Theoremtfrlemisucfn 5855* We can extend an acceptable function by one element to produce a function. Lemma for tfrlemi1 5863. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Jul-2019.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}    &   (φx(Fun 𝐹 (𝐹x) V))    &   (φz On)    &   (φg Fn z)    &   (φg A)       (φ → (g ∪ {⟨z, (𝐹g)⟩}) Fn suc z)
 
Theoremtfrlemisucaccv 5856* We can extend an acceptable function by one element to produce an acceptable function. Lemma for tfrlemi1 5863. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-Mar-2019.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}    &   (φx(Fun 𝐹 (𝐹x) V))    &   (φz On)    &   (φg Fn z)    &   (φg A)       (φ → (g ∪ {⟨z, (𝐹g)⟩}) A)
 
Theoremtfrlemibacc 5857* Each element of B is an acceptable function. Lemma for tfrlemi1 5863. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Mar-2019.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}    &   (φx(Fun 𝐹 (𝐹x) V))    &   B = {z x g(g Fn z g A = (g ∪ {⟨z, (𝐹g)⟩}))}    &   (φx On)    &   (φz x g(g Fn z w z (gw) = (𝐹‘(gw))))       (φBA)
 
Theoremtfrlemibxssdm 5858* The union of B is defined on all ordinals. Lemma for tfrlemi1 5863. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Mar-2019.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}    &   (φx(Fun 𝐹 (𝐹x) V))    &   B = {z x g(g Fn z g A = (g ∪ {⟨z, (𝐹g)⟩}))}    &   (φx On)    &   (φz x g(g Fn z w z (gw) = (𝐹‘(gw))))       (φx ⊆ dom B)
 
Theoremtfrlemibfn 5859* The union of B is a function defined on x. Lemma for tfrlemi1 5863. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Mar-2019.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}    &   (φx(Fun 𝐹 (𝐹x) V))    &   B = {z x g(g Fn z g A = (g ∪ {⟨z, (𝐹g)⟩}))}    &   (φx On)    &   (φz x g(g Fn z w z (gw) = (𝐹‘(gw))))       (φ B Fn x)
 
Theoremtfrlemibex 5860* The set B exists. Lemma for tfrlemi1 5863. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Mar-2019.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}    &   (φx(Fun 𝐹 (𝐹x) V))    &   B = {z x g(g Fn z g A = (g ∪ {⟨z, (𝐹g)⟩}))}    &   (φx On)    &   (φz x g(g Fn z w z (gw) = (𝐹‘(gw))))       (φB V)
 
Theoremtfrlemiubacc 5861* The union of B satisfies the recursion rule (lemma for tfrlemi1 5863). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 22-Apr-2019.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}    &   (φx(Fun 𝐹 (𝐹x) V))    &   B = {z x g(g Fn z g A = (g ∪ {⟨z, (𝐹g)⟩}))}    &   (φx On)    &   (φz x g(g Fn z w z (gw) = (𝐹‘(gw))))       (φu x ( Bu) = (𝐹‘( Bu)))
 
Theoremtfrlemiex 5862* Lemma for tfrlemi1 5863. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Mar-2019.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}    &   (φx(Fun 𝐹 (𝐹x) V))    &   B = {z x g(g Fn z g A = (g ∪ {⟨z, (𝐹g)⟩}))}    &   (φx On)    &   (φz x g(g Fn z w z (gw) = (𝐹‘(gw))))       (φf(f Fn x u x (fu) = (𝐹‘(fu))))
 
Theoremtfrlemi1 5863* We can define an acceptable function on any ordinal.

As with many of the transfinite recursion theorems, we have a hypothesis that states that 𝐹 is a function and that it is defined for all ordinals. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-Mar-2019.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.)

A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}    &   (φx(Fun 𝐹 (𝐹x) V))       ((φ 𝐶 On) → g(g Fn 𝐶 u 𝐶 (gu) = (𝐹‘(gu))))
 
Theoremtfrlemi14d 5864* The domain of recs is all ordinals (lemma for transfinite recursion). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 9-Jul-2019.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}    &   (φx(Fun 𝐹 (𝐹x) V))       (φ → dom recs(𝐹) = On)
 
Theoremtfrlemi14 5865* The domain of recs is all ordinals (lemma for transfinite recursion). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2019.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}    &   (Fun 𝐹 (𝐹x) V)       dom recs(𝐹) = On
 
Theoremtfrexlem 5866* The transfinite recursion function is set-like if the input is. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Jul-2019.)
A = {fx On (f Fn x y x (fy) = (𝐹‘(fy)))}    &   (φx(Fun 𝐹 (𝐹x) V))       ((φ 𝐶 𝑉) → (recs(𝐹)‘𝐶) V)
 
Theoremtfri1d 5867* Principle of Transfinite Recursion, part 1 of 3. Theorem 7.41(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 47, with an additional condition.

The condition is that 𝐺 is defined "everywhere" and here is stated as (𝐺x) V. Alternatively x Onf(f Fn xf dom 𝐺) would suffice.

Given a function 𝐺 satisfying that condition, we define a class A of all "acceptable" functions. The final function we're interested in is the union 𝐹 = recs(𝐺) of them. 𝐹 is then said to be defined by transfinite recursion. The purpose of the 3 parts of this theorem is to demonstrate properties of 𝐹. In this first part we show that 𝐹 is a function whose domain is all ordinal numbers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2019.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.)

𝐹 = recs(𝐺)    &   (φx(Fun 𝐺 (𝐺x) V))       (φ𝐹 Fn On)
 
Theoremtfri2d 5868* Principle of Transfinite Recursion, part 2 of 3. Theorem 7.41(2) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 47, with an additional condition on the recursion rule 𝐺 ( as described at tfri1 5869). Here we show that the function 𝐹 has the property that for any function 𝐺 satisfying that condition, the "next" value of 𝐹 is 𝐺 recursively applied to all "previous" values of 𝐹. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2019.)
𝐹 = recs(𝐺)    &   (φx(Fun 𝐺 (𝐺x) V))       ((φ A On) → (𝐹A) = (𝐺‘(𝐹A)))
 
Theoremtfri1 5869* Principle of Transfinite Recursion, part 1 of 3. Theorem 7.41(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 47, with an additional condition.

The condition is that 𝐺 is defined "everywhere" and here is stated as (𝐺x) V. Alternatively x Onf(f Fn xf dom 𝐺) would suffice.

Given a function 𝐺 satisfying that condition, we define a class A of all "acceptable" functions. The final function we're interested in is the union 𝐹 = recs(𝐺) of them. 𝐹 is then said to be defined by transfinite recursion. The purpose of the 3 parts of this theorem is to demonstrate properties of 𝐹. In this first part we show that 𝐹 is a function whose domain is all ordinal numbers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2019.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.)

𝐹 = recs(𝐺)    &   (Fun 𝐺 (𝐺x) V)       𝐹 Fn On
 
Theoremtfri2 5870* Principle of Transfinite Recursion, part 2 of 3. Theorem 7.41(2) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 47, with an additional condition on the recursion rule 𝐺 ( as described at tfri1 5869). Here we show that the function 𝐹 has the property that for any function 𝐺 satisfying that condition, the "next" value of 𝐹 is 𝐺 recursively applied to all "previous" values of 𝐹. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2019.)
𝐹 = recs(𝐺)    &   (Fun 𝐺 (𝐺x) V)       (A On → (𝐹A) = (𝐺‘(𝐹A)))
 
Theoremtfri3 5871* Principle of Transfinite Recursion, part 3 of 3. Theorem 7.41(3) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 47, with an additional condition on the recursion rule 𝐺 ( as described at tfri1 5869). Finally, we show that 𝐹 is unique. We do this by showing that any class B with the same properties of 𝐹 that we showed in parts 1 and 2 is identical to 𝐹. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2019.)
𝐹 = recs(𝐺)    &   (Fun 𝐺 (𝐺x) V)       ((B Fn On x On (Bx) = (𝐺‘(Bx))) → B = 𝐹)
 
Theoremtfrex 5872* The transfinite recursion function is set-like if the input is. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Jul-2019.)
𝐹 = recs(𝐺)    &   (φx(Fun 𝐺 (𝐺x) V))       ((φ A 𝑉) → (𝐹A) V)
 
2.6.20  Recursive definition generator
 
Syntaxcrdg 5873 Extend class notation with the recursive definition generator, with characteristic function 𝐹 and initial value 𝐼.
class rec(𝐹, 𝐼)
 
Definitiondf-irdg 5874* Define a recursive definition generator on On (the class of ordinal numbers) with characteristic function 𝐹 and initial value 𝐼. This rather amazing operation allows us to define, with compact direct definitions, functions that are usually defined in textbooks only with indirect self-referencing recursive definitions. A recursive definition requires advanced metalogic to justify - in particular, eliminating a recursive definition is very difficult and often not even shown in textbooks. On the other hand, the elimination of a direct definition is a matter of simple mechanical substitution. The price paid is the daunting complexity of our rec operation (especially when df-recs 5838 that it is built on is also eliminated). But once we get past this hurdle, definitions that would otherwise be recursive become relatively simple. In classical logic it would be easier to divide this definition into cases based on whether the domain of g is zero, a successor, or a limit ordinal. Cases do not (in general) work that way in intuitionistic logic, so instead we choose a definition which takes the union of all the results of the characteristic function for ordinals in the domain of g. This means that this definition has the expected properties for increasing and continuous ordinal functions, which include ordinal addition and multiplication.

For finite recursion we also define df-frec 5894 and for suitable characteristic functions df-frec 5894 yields the same result as rec restricted to 𝜔, as seen at frecrdg 5904.

Note: We introduce rec with the philosophical goal of being able to eliminate all definitions with direct mechanical substitution and to verify easily the soundness of definitions. Metamath itself has no built-in technical limitation that prevents multiple-part recursive definitions in the traditional textbook style. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-May-2019.)

rec(𝐹, 𝐼) = recs((g V ↦ (𝐼 x dom g(𝐹‘(gx)))))
 
Theoremrdgeq1 5875 Equality theorem for the recursive definition generator. (Contributed by NM, 9-Apr-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-May-2015.)
(𝐹 = 𝐺 → rec(𝐹, A) = rec(𝐺, A))
 
Theoremrdgeq2 5876 Equality theorem for the recursive definition generator. (Contributed by NM, 9-Apr-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-May-2015.)
(A = B → rec(𝐹, A) = rec(𝐹, B))
 
Theoremrdgfun 5877 The recursive definition generator is a function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Nov-2014.)
Fun rec(𝐹, A)
 
Theoremrdgruledefgg 5878* The recursion rule for the recursive definition generator is defined everywhere. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-Jul-2019.)
((𝐹 Fn V A 𝑉) → (Fun (g V ↦ (A x dom g(𝐹‘(gx)))) ((g V ↦ (A x dom g(𝐹‘(gx))))‘f) V))
 
Theoremrdgruledefg 5879* The recursion rule for the recursive definition generator is defined everywhere. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-Jul-2019.)
𝐹 Fn V       (A 𝑉 → (Fun (g V ↦ (A x dom g(𝐹‘(gx)))) ((g V ↦ (A x dom g(𝐹‘(gx))))‘f) V))
 
Theoremrdgexggg 5880 The recursive definition generator produces a set on a set input. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-Jul-2019.)
((𝐹 Fn V A 𝑉 B 𝑊) → (rec(𝐹, A)‘B) V)
 
Theoremrdgexgg 5881 The recursive definition generator produces a set on a set input. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-Jul-2019.)
𝐹 Fn V       ((A 𝑉 B 𝑊) → (rec(𝐹, A)‘B) V)
 
Theoremrdgi0g 5882 The initial value of the recursive definition generator. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 10-Jul-2019.)
((𝐹 Fn V A 𝑉) → (rec(𝐹, A)‘∅) = A)
 
Theoremrdgifnon 5883 The recursive definition generator is a function on ordinal numbers. The 𝐹 Fn V condition states that the characteristic function is defined for all sets (being defined for all ordinals might be enough, but being defined for all sets will generally hold for the characteristic functions we need to use this with). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-Jul-2019.)
((𝐹 Fn V A 𝑉) → rec(𝐹, A) Fn On)
 
Theoremrdgivallem 5884* Value of the recursive definition generator. Lemma for rdgival 5885 which simplifies the value further. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.)
((𝐹 Fn V A 𝑉 B On) → (rec(𝐹, A)‘B) = (A x B (𝐹‘((rec(𝐹, A) ↾ B)‘x))))
 
Theoremrdgival 5885* Value of the recursive definition generator. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Jul-2019.)
((𝐹 Fn V A 𝑉 B On) → (rec(𝐹, A)‘B) = (A x B (𝐹‘(rec(𝐹, A)‘x))))
 
Theoremrdgss 5886 Subset and recursive definition generator. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Jul-2019.)
(φ𝐹 Fn V)    &   (φ𝐼 𝑉)    &   (φA On)    &   (φB On)    &   (φAB)       (φ → (rec(𝐹, 𝐼)‘A) ⊆ (rec(𝐹, 𝐼)‘B))
 
Theoremrdgisuc1 5887* One way of describing the value of the recursive definition generator at a successor. There is no condition on the characteristic function 𝐹 other than 𝐹 Fn V. Given that, the resulting expression encompasses both the expected successor term (𝐹‘(rec(𝐹, A)‘B)) but also terms that correspond to the initial value A and to limit ordinals x B(𝐹‘(rec(𝐹, A)‘x)).

If we add conditions on the characteristic function, we can show tighter results such as rdgisucinc 5888. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 9-Jun-2019.)

(φ𝐹 Fn V)    &   (φA 𝑉)    &   (φB On)       (φ → (rec(𝐹, A)‘suc B) = (A ∪ ( x B (𝐹‘(rec(𝐹, A)‘x)) ∪ (𝐹‘(rec(𝐹, A)‘B)))))
 
Theoremrdgisucinc 5888* Value of the recursive definition generator at a successor.

This can be thought of as a generalization of oasuc 5955 and omsuc 5962. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Aug-2019.)

(φ𝐹 Fn V)    &   (φA 𝑉)    &   (φB On)    &   (φx x ⊆ (𝐹x))       (φ → (rec(𝐹, A)‘suc B) = (𝐹‘(rec(𝐹, A)‘B)))
 
Theoremrdgon 5889* Evaluating the recursive definition generator produces an ordinal. There is a hypothesis that the characteristic function produces ordinals on ordinal arguments. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Jul-2019.)
(φ𝐹 Fn V)    &   (φA On)    &   (φx On (𝐹x) On)       ((φ B On) → (rec(𝐹, A)‘B) On)
 
Theoremrdgruledef 5890* The recursion rule for the recursive definition generator is defined everywhere. Lemma for rdg0 5891. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-May-2019.)
A V    &   𝐹 Fn V       (Fun (g V ↦ (A x dom g(𝐹‘(gx)))) ((g V ↦ (A x dom g(𝐹‘(gx))))‘f) V)
 
Theoremrdg0 5891 The initial value of the recursive definition generator. (Contributed by NM, 23-Apr-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Nov-2014.)
A V    &   𝐹 Fn V       (rec(𝐹, A)‘∅) = A
 
Theoremrdgexg 5892 The recursive definition generator produces a set on a set input. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Jul-2019.)
A V    &   𝐹 Fn V       (B 𝑉 → (rec(𝐹, A)‘B) V)
 
2.6.21  Finite recursion
 
Syntaxcfrec 5893 Extend class notation with the fnite recursive definition generator, with characteristic function 𝐹 and initial value 𝐼.
class frec(𝐹, 𝐼)
 
Definitiondf-frec 5894* Define a recursive definition generator on 𝜔 (the class of finite ordinals) with characteristic function 𝐹 and initial value 𝐼. This rather amazing operation allows us to define, with compact direct definitions, functions that are usually defined in textbooks only with indirect self-referencing recursive definitions. A recursive definition requires advanced metalogic to justify - in particular, eliminating a recursive definition is very difficult and often not even shown in textbooks. On the other hand, the elimination of a direct definition is a matter of simple mechanical substitution. The price paid is the daunting complexity of our frec operation (especially when df-recs 5838 that it is built on is also eliminated). But once we get past this hurdle, definitions that would otherwise be recursive become relatively simple; see frec0g 5898 and frecsuc 5903.

Unlike with transfinite recursion, finite recurson can readily divide definitions and proofs into zero and successor cases, because even without excluded middle we have theorems such as nn0suc 4250. The analogous situation with transfinite recursion - being able to say that an ordinal is zero, successor, or limit - is enabled by excluded middle and thus is not available to us. For the characteristic functions which satisfy the conditions given at frecrdg 5904, this definition and df-irdg 5874 restricted to 𝜔 produce the same result.

Note: We introduce frec with the philosophical goal of being able to eliminate all definitions with direct mechanical substitution and to verify easily the soundness of definitions. Metamath itself has no built-in technical limitation that prevents multiple-part recursive definitions in the traditional textbook style. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 10-Aug-2019.)

frec(𝐹, 𝐼) = (recs((g V ↦ {x ∣ (𝑚 𝜔 (dom g = suc 𝑚 x (𝐹‘(g𝑚))) (dom g = ∅ x 𝐼))})) ↾ 𝜔)
 
Theoremfrecabex 5895* The class abstraction from df-frec 5894 exists. This is a lemma for several other finite recursion proofs. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Aug-2019.)
(φ𝑆 𝑉)    &   (φ𝐹 Fn V)    &   (φA 𝑊)       (φ → {x ∣ (𝑚 𝜔 (dom 𝑆 = suc 𝑚 x (𝐹‘(𝑆𝑚))) (dom 𝑆 = ∅ x A))} V)
 
Theoremfrectfr 5896* Lemma to connect transfinite recursion theorems with finite recursion. That is, given the conditions 𝐹 Fn V and A 𝑉 on frec(𝐹, A), we want to be able to apply tfri1d 5867 or tfri2d 5868, and this lemma lets us satisfy hypotheses of those theorems.

(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Aug-2019.)

𝐺 = (g V ↦ {x ∣ (𝑚 𝜔 (dom g = suc 𝑚 x (𝐹‘(g𝑚))) (dom g = ∅ x A))})       ((𝐹 Fn V A 𝑉) → y(Fun 𝐺 (𝐺y) V))
 
Theoremfrecfnom 5897 The function generated by finite recursive definition generation is a function on omega. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-Aug-2019.)
((𝐹 Fn V A 𝑉) → frec(𝐹, A) Fn 𝜔)
 
Theoremfrec0g 5898 The initial value resulting from finite recursive definition generation. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-Aug-2019.)
((𝐹 Fn V A 𝑉) → (frec(𝐹, A)‘∅) = A)
 
Theoremfrecsuclem1 5899* Lemma for frecsuc 5903. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-Aug-2019.)
𝐺 = (g V ↦ {x ∣ (𝑚 𝜔 (dom g = suc 𝑚 x (𝐹‘(g𝑚))) (dom g = ∅ x A))})       ((𝐹 Fn V A 𝑉 B 𝜔) → (frec(𝐹, A)‘suc B) = (𝐺‘(recs(𝐺) ↾ suc B)))
 
Theoremfrecsuclemdm 5900* Lemma for frecsuc 5903. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Aug-2019.)
𝐺 = (g V ↦ {x ∣ (𝑚 𝜔 (dom g = suc 𝑚 x (𝐹‘(g𝑚))) (dom g = ∅ x A))})       ((𝐹 Fn V A 𝑉 B 𝜔) → dom (recs(𝐺) ↾ suc B) = suc B)
    < Previous  Next >

Page List
Jump to page: Contents  1 1-100 2 101-200 3 201-300 4 301-400 5 401-500 6 501-600 7 601-700 8 701-800 9 801-900 10 901-1000 11 1001-1100 12 1101-1200 13 1201-1300 14 1301-1400 15 1401-1500 16 1501-1600 17 1601-1700 18 1701-1800 19 1801-1900 20 1901-2000 21 2001-2100 22 2101-2200 23 2201-2300 24 2301-2400 25 2401-2500 26 2501-2600 27 2601-2700 28 2701-2800 29 2801-2900 30 2901-3000 31 3001-3100 32 3101-3200 33 3201-3300 34 3301-3400 35 3401-3500 36 3501-3600 37 3601-3700 38 3701-3800 39 3801-3900 40 3901-4000 41 4001-4100 42 4101-4200 43 4201-4300 44 4301-4400 45 4401-4500 46 4501-4600 47 4601-4700 48 4701-4800 49 4801-4900 50 4901-5000 51 5001-5100 52 5101-5200 53 5201-5300 54 5301-5400 55 5401-5500 56 5501-5600 57 5601-5700 58 5701-5800 59 5801-5900 60 5901-6000 61 6001-6100 62 6101-6200 63 6201-6300 64 6301-6400 65 6401-6500 66 6501-6600 67 6601-6700 68 6701-6800 69 6801-6900 70 6901-7000 71 7001-7100 72 7101-7200 73 7201-7300 74 7301-7354
  Copyright terms: Public domain < Previous  Next >