HomeHome Intuitionistic Logic Explorer
Theorem List (p. 17 of 73)
< Previous  Next >
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version.

Mirrors  >  Metamath Home Page  >  ILE Home Page  >  Theorem List Contents  >  Recent Proofs       This page: Page List

Theorem List for Intuitionistic Logic Explorer - 1601-1700   *Has distinct variable group(s)
TypeLabelDescription
Statement
 
Theoremdral2 1601 Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 27-Feb-2005.)
(x x = y → (φψ))       (x x = y → (zφzψ))
 
Theoremdrex2 1602 Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 27-Feb-2005.)
(x x = y → (φψ))       (x x = y → (zφzψ))
 
Theoremdrnf1 1603 Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.)
(x x = y → (φψ))       (x x = y → (Ⅎxφ ↔ Ⅎyψ))
 
Theoremdrnf2 1604 Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.)
(x x = y → (φψ))       (x x = y → (Ⅎzφ ↔ Ⅎzψ))
 
Theoremspimth 1605 Closed theorem form of spim 1608. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jan-2008.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(x((ψxψ) (x = y → (φψ))) → (xφψ))
 
Theoremspimt 1606 Closed theorem form of spim 1608. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jan-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 24-Feb-2018.)
((Ⅎxψ x(x = y → (φψ))) → (xφψ))
 
Theoremspimh 1607 Specialization, using implicit substitition. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. The spim 1608 series of theorems requires that only one direction of the substitution hypothesis hold. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 8-May-2008.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(ψxψ)    &   (x = y → (φψ))       (xφψ)
 
Theoremspim 1608 Specialization, using implicit substitution. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. The spim 1608 series of theorems requires that only one direction of the substitution hypothesis hold. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 10-Jun-2018.)
xψ    &   (x = y → (φψ))       (xφψ)
 
Theoremspimeh 1609 Existential introduction, using implicit substitition. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(φxφ)    &   (x = y → (φψ))       (φxψ)
 
Theoremspimed 1610 Deduction version of spime 1611. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 19-Feb-2018.)
(χ → Ⅎxφ)    &   (x = y → (φψ))       (χ → (φxψ))
 
Theoremspime 1611 Existential introduction, using implicit substitution. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 6-Mar-2018.)
xφ    &   (x = y → (φψ))       (φxψ)
 
Theoremcbv3 1612 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-May-2018.)
yφ    &   xψ    &   (x = y → (φψ))       (xφyψ)
 
Theoremcbv3h 1613 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-May-2018.)
(φyφ)    &   (ψxψ)    &   (x = y → (φψ))       (xφyψ)
 
Theoremcbv1 1614 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Revised to format hypotheses to common style. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2018.)
xφ    &   yφ    &   (φ → Ⅎyψ)    &   (φ → Ⅎxχ)    &   (φ → (x = y → (ψχ)))       (φ → (xψyχ))
 
Theoremcbv1h 1615 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2018.)
(φ → (ψyψ))    &   (φ → (χxχ))    &   (φ → (x = y → (ψχ)))       (xyφ → (xψyχ))
 
Theoremcbv2h 1616 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(φ → (ψyψ))    &   (φ → (χxχ))    &   (φ → (x = y → (ψχ)))       (xyφ → (xψyχ))
 
Theoremcbv2 1617 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Revised to align format of hypotheses to common style. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2018.)
xφ    &   yφ    &   (φ → Ⅎyψ)    &   (φ → Ⅎxχ)    &   (φ → (x = y → (ψχ)))       (φ → (xψyχ))
 
Theoremcbvalh 1618 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitition. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.)
(φyφ)    &   (ψxψ)    &   (x = y → (φψ))       (xφyψ)
 
Theoremcbval 1619 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.)
yφ    &   xψ    &   (x = y → (φψ))       (xφyψ)
 
Theoremcbvexh 1620 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitition. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Feb-2015.)
(φyφ)    &   (ψxψ)    &   (x = y → (φψ))       (xφyψ)
 
Theoremcbvex 1621 Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
yφ    &   xψ    &   (x = y → (φψ))       (xφyψ)
 
Theoremchvar 1622 Implicit substitution of y for x into a theorem. (Contributed by Raph Levien, 9-Jul-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.)
xψ    &   (x = y → (φψ))    &   φ       ψ
 
Theoremequvini 1623 A variable introduction law for equality. Lemma 15 of [Monk2] p. 109, however we do not require z to be distinct from x and y (making the proof longer). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.)
(x = yz(x = z z = y))
 
Theoremequveli 1624 A variable elimination law for equality with no distinct variable requirements. (Compare equvini 1623.) (Contributed by NM, 1-Mar-2013.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.)
(z(z = xz = y) → x = y)
 
Theoremnfald 1625 If x is not free in φ, it is not free in yφ. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 6-Jan-2018.)
yφ    &   (φ → Ⅎxψ)       (φ → Ⅎxyψ)
 
Theoremnfexd 1626 If x is not free in φ, it is not free in yφ. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 7-Feb-2018.)
yφ    &   (φ → Ⅎxψ)       (φ → Ⅎxyψ)
 
1.3.10  Substitution (without distinct variables)
 
Syntaxwsb 1627 Extend wff definition to include proper substitution (read "the wff that results when y is properly substituted for x in wff φ"). (Contributed by NM, 24-Jan-2006.)
wff [y / x]φ
 
Definitiondf-sb 1628 Define proper substitution. Remark 9.1 in [Megill] p. 447 (p. 15 of the preprint). For our notation, we use [y / x]φ to mean "the wff that results when y is properly substituted for x in the wff φ." We can also use [y / x]φ in place of the "free for" side condition used in traditional predicate calculus; see, for example, stdpc4 1640.

Our notation was introduced in Haskell B. Curry's Foundations of Mathematical Logic (1977), p. 316 and is frequently used in textbooks of lambda calculus and combinatory logic. This notation improves the common but ambiguous notation, "φ(y) is the wff that results when y is properly substituted for x in φ(x)." For example, if the original φ(x) is x = y, then φ(y) is y = y, from which we obtain that φ(x) is x = x. So what exactly does φ(x) mean? Curry's notation solves this problem.

In most books, proper substitution has a somewhat complicated recursive definition with multiple cases based on the occurrences of free and bound variables in the wff. Instead, we use a single formula that is exactly equivalent and gives us a direct definition. We later prove that our definition has the properties we expect of proper substitution (see theorems sbequ 1703, sbcom2 1845 and sbid2v 1854).

Note that our definition is valid even when x and y are replaced with the same variable, as sbid 1639 shows. We achieve this by having x free in the first conjunct and bound in the second. We can also achieve this by using a dummy variable, as the alternate definition dfsb7 1849 shows (which some logicians may prefer because it doesn't mix free and bound variables). Another alternate definition which uses a dummy variable is dfsb7a 1852.

When x and y are distinct, we can express proper substitution with the simpler expressions of sb5 1749 and sb6 1748.

In classical logic, another possible definition is (x = y φ) x(x = yφ) but we do not have an intuitionistic proof that this is equivalent.

There are no restrictions on any of the variables, including what variables may occur in wff φ. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

([y / x]φ ↔ ((x = yφ) x(x = y φ)))
 
Theoremsbimi 1629 Infer substitution into antecedent and consequent of an implication. (Contributed by NM, 25-Jun-1998.)
(φψ)       ([y / x]φ → [y / x]ψ)
 
Theoremsbbii 1630 Infer substitution into both sides of a logical equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(φψ)       ([y / x]φ ↔ [y / x]ψ)
 
Theoremsb1 1631 One direction of a simplified definition of substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
([y / x]φx(x = y φ))
 
Theoremsb2 1632 One direction of a simplified definition of substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(x(x = yφ) → [y / x]φ)
 
Theoremsbequ1 1633 An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(x = y → (φ → [y / x]φ))
 
Theoremsbequ2 1634 An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(x = y → ([y / x]φφ))
 
Theoremstdpc7 1635 One of the two equality axioms of standard predicate calculus, called substitutivity of equality. (The other one is stdpc6 1573.) Translated to traditional notation, it can be read: "x = y → (φ(x, x) → φ(x, y)), provided that y is free for x in φ(x, y)." Axiom 7 of [Mendelson] p. 95. (Contributed by NM, 15-Feb-2005.)
(x = y → ([x / y]φφ))
 
Theoremsbequ12 1636 An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(x = y → (φ ↔ [y / x]φ))
 
Theoremsbequ12r 1637 An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 6-Oct-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 21-Jun-2011.)
(x = y → ([x / y]φφ))
 
Theoremsbequ12a 1638 An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(x = y → ([y / x]φ ↔ [x / y]φ))
 
Theoremsbid 1639 An identity theorem for substitution. Remark 9.1 in [Megill] p. 447 (p. 15 of the preprint). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
([x / x]φφ)
 
Theoremstdpc4 1640 The specialization axiom of standard predicate calculus. It states that if a statement φ holds for all x, then it also holds for the specific case of y (properly) substituted for x. Translated to traditional notation, it can be read: "xφ(x) → φ(y), provided that y is free for x in φ(x)." Axiom 4 of [Mendelson] p. 69. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(xφ → [y / x]φ)
 
Theoremsbh 1641 Substitution for a variable not free in a wff does not affect it. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 17-Oct-2004.)
(φxφ)       ([y / x]φφ)
 
Theoremsbf 1642 Substitution for a variable not free in a wff does not affect it. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.)
xφ       ([y / x]φφ)
 
Theoremsbf2 1643 Substitution has no effect on a bound variable. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jul-2005.)
([y / x]xφxφ)
 
Theoremsb6x 1644 Equivalence involving substitution for a variable not free. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.)
(φxφ)       ([y / x]φx(x = yφ))
 
Theoremnfs1f 1645 If x is not free in φ, it is not free in [y / x]φ. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
xφ       x[y / x]φ
 
Theoremhbs1f 1646 If x is not free in φ, it is not free in [y / x]φ. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.)
(φxφ)       ([y / x]φx[y / x]φ)
 
Theoremsbequ5 1647 Substitution does not change an identical variable specifier. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 21-Dec-2004.)
([w / z]x x = yx x = y)
 
Theoremsbequ6 1648 Substitution does not change a distinctor. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 14-May-2005.)
([w / z] ¬ x x = y ↔ ¬ x x = y)
 
Theoremsbt 1649 A substitution into a theorem remains true. (See chvar 1622 and chvarv 1794 for versions using implicit substitition.) (Contributed by NM, 21-Jan-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.)
φ       [y / x]φ
 
Theoremequsb1 1650 Substitution applied to an atomic wff. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
[y / x]x = y
 
Theoremequsb2 1651 Substitution applied to an atomic wff. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
[y / x]y = x
 
Theoremsbiedh 1652 Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution (deduction version of sbieh 1655). New proofs should use sbied 1653 instead. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-1994.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(φxφ)    &   (φ → (χxχ))    &   (φ → (x = y → (ψχ)))       (φ → ([y / x]ψχ))
 
Theoremsbied 1653 Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution (deduction version of sbie 1656). (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.)
xφ    &   (φ → Ⅎxχ)    &   (φ → (x = y → (ψχ)))       (φ → ([y / x]ψχ))
 
Theoremsbiedv 1654* Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution (deduction version of sbie 1656). (Contributed by NM, 7-Jan-2017.)
((φ x = y) → (ψχ))       (φ → ([y / x]ψχ))
 
Theoremsbieh 1655 Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution. New proofs should use sbie 1656 instead. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-1994.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(ψxψ)    &   (x = y → (φψ))       ([y / x]φψ)
 
Theoremsbie 1656 Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 30-Apr-2018.)
xψ    &   (x = y → (φψ))       ([y / x]φψ)
 
1.3.11  Theorems using axiom ax-11
 
Theoremequs5a 1657 A property related to substitution that unlike equs5 1692 doesn't require a distinctor antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.)
(x(x = y yφ) → x(x = yφ))
 
Theoremequs5e 1658 A property related to substitution that unlike equs5 1692 doesn't require a distinctor antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.)
(x(x = y φ) → x(x = yyφ))
 
Theoremax11e 1659 Analogue to ax-11 1378 but for existential quantification. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 31-Dec-2017.) (Proved by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2018.)
(x = y → (x(x = y φ) → yφ))
 
Theoremax10oe 1660 Quantifier Substitution for existential quantifiers. Analogue to ax10o 1585 but for rather than . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 21-Dec-2017.)
(x x = y → (xψyψ))
 
Theoremdrex1 1661 Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 27-Feb-2005.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.)
(x x = y → (φψ))       (x x = y → (xφyψ))
 
Theoremdrsb1 1662 Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(x x = y → ([z / x]φ ↔ [z / y]φ))
 
Theoremexdistrfor 1663 Distribution of existential quantifiers, with a bound-variable hypothesis saying that y is not free in φ, but x can be free in φ (and there is no distinct variable condition on x and y). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Feb-2018.)
(x x = y xyφ)       (xy(φ ψ) → x(φ yψ))
 
Theoremsb4a 1664 A version of sb4 1695 that doesn't require a distinctor antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.)
([y / x]yφx(x = yφ))
 
Theoremequs45f 1665 Two ways of expressing substitution when y is not free in φ. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-2008.)
(φyφ)       (x(x = y φ) ↔ x(x = yφ))
 
Theoremsb6f 1666 Equivalence for substitution when y is not free in φ. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 30-Apr-2008.)
(φyφ)       ([y / x]φx(x = yφ))
 
Theoremsb5f 1667 Equivalence for substitution when y is not free in φ. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 18-May-2008.)
(φyφ)       ([y / x]φx(x = y φ))
 
Theoremsb4e 1668 One direction of a simplified definition of substitution that unlike sb4 1695 doesn't require a distinctor antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.)
([y / x]φx(x = yyφ))
 
Theoremhbsb2a 1669 Special case of a bound-variable hypothesis builder for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.)
([y / x]yφx[y / x]φ)
 
Theoremhbsb2e 1670 Special case of a bound-variable hypothesis builder for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.)
([y / x]φx[y / x]yφ)
 
Theoremhbsb3 1671 If y is not free in φ, x is not free in [y / x]φ. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(φyφ)       ([y / x]φx[y / x]φ)
 
Theoremnfs1 1672 If y is not free in φ, x is not free in [y / x]φ. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
yφ       x[y / x]φ
 
Theoremsbcof2 1673 Version of sbco 1824 where x is not free in φ. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Dec-2017.)
(φxφ)       ([y / x][x / y]φ ↔ [y / x]φ)
 
1.4  Predicate calculus with distinct variables
 
1.4.1  Derive the axiom of distinct variables ax-16
 
Theoremspimv 1674* A version of spim 1608 with a distinct variable requirement instead of a bound variable hypothesis. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(x = y → (φψ))       (xφψ)
 
Theoremaev 1675* A "distinctor elimination" lemma with no restrictions on variables in the consequent, proved without using ax-16 1677. (Contributed by NM, 8-Nov-2006.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 21-Jun-2011.)
(x x = yz w = v)
 
Theoremax16 1676* Theorem showing that ax-16 1677 is redundant if ax-17 1400 is included in the axiom system. The important part of the proof is provided by aev 1675.

See ax16ALT 1721 for an alternate proof that does not require ax-10 1377 or ax-12 1383.

This theorem should not be referenced in any proof. Instead, use ax-16 1677 below so that theorems needing ax-16 1677 can be more easily identified. (Contributed by NM, 8-Nov-2006.)

(x x = y → (φxφ))
 
Axiomax-16 1677* Axiom of Distinct Variables. The only axiom of predicate calculus requiring that variables be distinct (if we consider ax-17 1400 to be a metatheorem and not an axiom). Axiom scheme C16' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). It apparently does not otherwise appear in the literature but is easily proved from textbook predicate calculus by cases. It is a somewhat bizarre axiom since the antecedent is always false in set theory, but nonetheless it is technically necessary as you can see from its uses.

This axiom is redundant if we include ax-17 1400; see theorem ax16 1676.

This axiom is obsolete and should no longer be used. It is proved above as theorem ax16 1676. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)

(x x = y → (φxφ))
 
Theoremdveeq2 1678* Quantifier introduction when one pair of variables is distinct. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.)
x x = y → (z = yx z = y))
 
Theoremdveeq2or 1679* Quantifier introduction when one pair of variables is distinct. Like dveeq2 1678 but connecting xx = y by a disjunction rather than negation and implication makes the theorem stronger in intuitionistic logic. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 1-Feb-2018.)
(x x = y x z = y)
 
TheoremdvelimfALT2 1680* Proof of dvelimf 1873 using dveeq2 1678 (shown as the last hypothesis) instead of ax-12 1383. This shows that ax-12 1383 could be replaced by dveeq2 1678 (the last hypothesis). (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 21-Jul-2011.)
(φxφ)    &   (ψzψ)    &   (z = y → (φψ))    &   x x = y → (z = yx z = y))       x x = y → (ψxψ))
 
Theoremnd5 1681* A lemma for proving conditionless ZFC axioms. (Contributed by NM, 8-Jan-2002.)
y y = x → (z = yx z = y))
 
Theoremexlimdv 1682* Deduction from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 27-Apr-1994.)
(φ → (ψχ))       (φ → (xψχ))
 
Theoremax11v2 1683* Recovery of ax11o 1685 from ax11v 1690 without using ax-11 1378. The hypothesis is even weaker than ax11v 1690, with z both distinct from x and not occurring in φ. Thus the hypothesis provides an alternate axiom that can be used in place of ax11o 1685. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.)
(x = z → (φx(x = zφ)))       x x = y → (x = y → (φx(x = yφ))))
 
Theoremax11a2 1684* Derive ax-11o 1686 from a hypothesis in the form of ax-11 1378. The hypothesis is even weaker than ax-11 1378, with z both distinct from x and not occurring in φ. Thus the hypothesis provides an alternate axiom that can be used in place of ax11o 1685. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.)
(x = z → (zφx(x = zφ)))       x x = y → (x = y → (φx(x = yφ))))
 
1.4.2  Derive the obsolete axiom of variable substitution ax-11o
 
Theoremax11o 1685 Derivation of set.mm's original ax-11o 1686 from the shorter ax-11 1378 that has replaced it.

An open problem is whether this theorem can be proved without relying on ax-16 1677 or ax-17 1400.

Normally, ax11o 1685 should be used rather than ax-11o 1686, except by theorems specifically studying the latter's properties. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2007.)

x x = y → (x = y → (φx(x = yφ))))
 
Axiomax-11o 1686 Axiom ax-11o 1686 ("o" for "old") was the original version of ax-11 1378, before it was discovered (in Jan. 2007) that the shorter ax-11 1378 could replace it. It appears as Axiom scheme C15' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). It is based on Lemma 16 of [Tarski] p. 70 and Axiom C8 of [Monk2] p. 105, from which it can be proved by cases. To understand this theorem more easily, think of "¬ xx = y..." as informally meaning "if x and y are distinct variables then..." The antecedent becomes false if the same variable is substituted for x and y, ensuring the theorem is sound whenever this is the case. In some later theorems, we call an antecedent of the form ¬ xx = y a "distinctor."

This axiom is redundant, as shown by theorem ax11o 1685.

This axiom is obsolete and should no longer be used. It is proved above as theorem ax11o 1685. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)

x x = y → (x = y → (φx(x = yφ))))
 
1.4.3  More theorems related to ax-11 and substitution
 
Theoremalbidv 1687* Formula-building rule for universal quantifier (deduction rule). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(φ → (ψχ))       (φ → (xψxχ))
 
Theoremexbidv 1688* Formula-building rule for existential quantifier (deduction rule). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(φ → (ψχ))       (φ → (xψxχ))
 
Theoremax11b 1689 A bidirectional version of ax-11o 1686. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-2006.)
((¬ x x = y x = y) → (φx(x = yφ)))
 
Theoremax11v 1690* This is a version of ax-11o 1686 when the variables are distinct. Axiom (C8) of [Monk2] p. 105. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 15-Dec-2017.)
(x = y → (φx(x = yφ)))
 
Theoremax11ev 1691* Analogue to ax11v 1690 for existential quantification. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 9-Jan-2018.)
(x = y → (x(x = y φ) → φ))
 
Theoremequs5 1692 Lemma used in proofs of substitution properties. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
x x = y → (x(x = y φ) → x(x = yφ)))
 
Theoremequs5or 1693 Lemma used in proofs of substitution properties. Like equs5 1692 but, in intuitionistic logic, replacing negation and implication with disjunction makes this a stronger result. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Feb-2018.)
(x x = y (x(x = y φ) → x(x = yφ)))
 
Theoremsb3 1694 One direction of a simplified definition of substitution when variables are distinct. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
x x = y → (x(x = y φ) → [y / x]φ))
 
Theoremsb4 1695 One direction of a simplified definition of substitution when variables are distinct. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
x x = y → ([y / x]φx(x = yφ)))
 
Theoremsb4or 1696 One direction of a simplified definition of substitution when variables are distinct. Similar to sb4 1695 but stronger in intuitionistic logic. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Feb-2018.)
(x x = y x([y / x]φx(x = yφ)))
 
Theoremsb4b 1697 Simplified definition of substitution when variables are distinct. (Contributed by NM, 27-May-1997.)
x x = y → ([y / x]φx(x = yφ)))
 
Theoremsb4bor 1698 Simplified definition of substitution when variables are distinct, expressed via disjunction. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Mar-2018.)
(x x = y x([y / x]φx(x = yφ)))
 
Theoremhbsb2 1699 Bound-variable hypothesis builder for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
x x = y → ([y / x]φx[y / x]φ))
 
Theoremnfsb2or 1700 Bound-variable hypothesis builder for substitution. Similar to hbsb2 1699 but in intuitionistic logic a disjunction is stronger than an implication. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Feb-2018.)
(x x = y x[y / x]φ)
    < Previous  Next >

Page List
Jump to page: Contents  1 1-100 2 101-200 3 201-300 4 301-400 5 401-500 6 501-600 7 601-700 8 701-800 9 801-900 10 901-1000 11 1001-1100 12 1101-1200 13 1201-1300 14 1301-1400 15 1401-1500 16 1501-1600 17 1601-1700 18 1701-1800 19 1801-1900 20 1901-2000 21 2001-2100 22 2101-2200 23 2201-2300 24 2301-2400 25 2401-2500 26 2501-2600 27 2601-2700 28 2701-2800 29 2801-2900 30 2901-3000 31 3001-3100 32 3101-3200 33 3201-3300 34 3301-3400 35 3401-3500 36 3501-3600 37 3601-3700 38 3701-3800 39 3801-3900 40 3901-4000 41 4001-4100 42 4101-4200 43 4201-4300 44 4301-4400 45 4401-4500 46 4501-4600 47 4601-4700 48 4701-4800 49 4801-4900 50 4901-5000 51 5001-5100 52 5101-5200 53 5201-5300 54 5301-5400 55 5401-5500 56 5501-5600 57 5601-5700 58 5701-5800 59 5801-5900 60 5901-6000 61 6001-6100 62 6101-6200 63 6201-6300 64 6301-6400 65 6401-6500 66 6501-6600 67 6601-6700 68 6701-6800 69 6801-6900 70 6901-7000 71 7001-7100 72 7101-7200 73 7201-7215
  Copyright terms: Public domain < Previous  Next >